Carl E Schneider
The MIT Press
(NB: I was commissioned to review this book for Pacific Standard in September; what's published here is the first draft, from early October. After some suggestions from the editor, I submitted a revised second draft a couple of days later. Neither draft has been published there yet, and I've no idea if and when that will change. If anything does appear there, I'll provide a link.)
Not so long ago, Stephen Pinker provoked the ire of many
bioethicists by appearing to launch an attack on institutional ethical review
boards (IRBs). Accusing them of
hindering important work in science, he
wrote that they should “get out of the way”. Bioethicists responded by pointing out that there is a
history of researchers behaving abominably – the go-to example in recent years
being the Tuskegee syphilis study, in which black men were deliberately left
untreated so that the natural course of the disease could be studied. Ethical review, the bioethicists’
response goes, will not guarantee that nothing bad will ever happen; but it
does reduce the chance.
Yet Pinker’s broad claim is not without support from within the
bioethics community. Thoughtful
commentators have been looking at the institutional review board system for
some while now, and arguing that it needs significant reform. Could it be, some have wondered, that “bioethics” has become an end in itself, claiming an
authority with which even many bioethicists are uncomfortable? And if, then, there is a decent case
for reform, how far should it go?
Some think that the system needs re-tuning; some think that it needs
something approaching a rebuild.
And some think that a rebuild is too conservative: that the system is,
and cannot but be, so broken that the only option is to get rid of it all
together. In this camp, we find
Carl Schneider. The Censor’s Hand aims to present the
case not against IRBs as they are, but against IRBs tout court.
Schneider presents seven basic charges. IRBs, he posits, cannot be shown to do
good; can be shown to do harm; are built to err; overtax and have unrealistically
high expectations of their members; lack a “legible and convincing ethics”;
overdo informed consent; and corrode free expression (p 185). Throughout the book, he provides
example after example that are meant to demonstrate that these posits are true. And, indeed, some do have some merit. Sometimes ethics committees are staffed
by people who really don’t understand what they’re doing; they can get bogged
down in the minutiae of informed consent; and so on. More: the laws that set the terms within which ethics
committees work have to be phrased fairly broadly in order to be workable;
combine this with the fact that there is (in many countries) no overarching
organisation to manage them, and the absence of a uniform ethic is unsurprising
(though one man’s incoherence is another man’s flexibility and a third’s admirable
diversity).
But we cannot leap from any of that to the conclusion that
the IRB system should not be reformed or replaced but ditched; and some of the
accusations are not well-founded anyway.
A failure to research some illness does not cause death – the illness does that. Sure, IRBs cannot easily be shown to do good; but happiness
writes white: noone speaks publicly about IRBs making sensible suggestions and
working efficiently, and it’s hard to know much about disasters that didn’t
happen. Sometimes, concerns about
a given study may appear overwrought; but they may be defensible when seen as
the application of a broad principle about protecting the vulnerable. Schneider does a good enough job of
providing a platform for complainants, but he does not (and I think does not
seek to) provide an objective survey.
The complaint about censorship is – as far as I can make out – simply tendentious. Bluntly: not to get ethics committee approval for a study is not being censored. There’s no complex argument needed here: it just ain’t. It’s perplexing, too, that one of the (unreferenced) quotations used to make the assertion that IRBs’ function is “offensive… to the values protected by the First Amendment [and] a free society” (p 183) actually refers to Watchtower v Stratton, a case concerning door-to-door advocacy. Unless one thinks (implausibly, I’d suggest) that that and research are effectively the same thing, much more would have to be done to show that the point translates.
Schneider’s suggested alternatives to IRBs are bizarre. For him, research funders can act as
ethical gatekeepers (he doesn’t even acknowledge any conflicts of interest
here); and if something does go wrong, “injured subjects may sue researchers
for damages” or avail themselves of criminal sanctions (pp xxx, 195) – which is
paper-thin protection, provided much too late in the game.
Schneider does himself no favours in his presentation of an
already weak case. His targets are
personified as “regulationists”: a spooky band that seems to be comprised of
meddling do-gooders of whom all right-thinking people naturally disapprove; but
in this, he has done nothing more than to construct an Aunt Sally. And a direct result of the prioritisation
of complaint over balanced argument is that the book is, sadly, often almost unreadably
boring. Points are laboured rather than developed, and much of the
book is a parade of quotations that bludgeons the reader. There are 1084 references within this
fairly short work; the effect is dizzying rather than illuminating. Worse, not every quotation is clearly
or accurately referenced: one passage (p 52) talks about research on adolescent
sexuality and on drugs for childhood asthma, with quotations about both, though
but no reference is provided for the former topic. Elsewhere, a comment about the role of IRBs in the
gene-therapy trial that killed Jesse Gelsinger (p 122) is supported by a
quotation attributed to the Oxford bioethicist Julian Savulescu, but that is actually
from a 2004 paper by Richard Saver, who gets no credit. (The quotation, incidentally, seems to
say the opposite of what Schneider thinks it does.) This is a very poor show.
The Censor’s Hand
is likely to appeal to True Believers in the abolitionist cause; but whether it
would persuade anyone else is uncertain.
A more careful and measured presentation of the case would have helped
with that. As it is, it’s not at
all obvious whether those whose minds people like Schneider would need to
change would have the patience to finish the book.
No comments:
Post a Comment